64 found
Order:
  1.  89
    Character.Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Politicians, preachers, and ordinary people speak often of character; psychologists study `personality', used as a term of art with meanings close to `character'. Most ethical philosophers in the last two hundred years, on the other hand, have not had much to say about character. This book attempts to understand character and to refocus ethical philosophy so that character is central.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  2. The indispensability of character.Joel J. Kupperman - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (2):239-250.
    Gilbert Harman has argued that it does not make sense to ascribe character traits to people. The notion of morally virtuous character becomes particularly suspect. How plausible this is depends on how broad character traits would have to be. Views of character as entirely invariant behavioural tendencies offer a soft target. This paper explores a view that is a less easy target: character traits as specific to kinds of situation, and as involving probabilities or real possibilities. Such ascriptions are not (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  3. PART 4 107 Weakness and integrity 8 Moral growth and the unity of the virtues 109.Bonnie Kent, Jan Steutel, David Carr, John Haldane, Paul Crittenden, Eamonn Callan, Joel J. Kupperman, Ben Spiecker & Kenneth A. Strike - 1999 - In David Carr & Jan Willem Steutel (eds.), Virtue ethics and moral education. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  4. Virtue in Virtue Ethics.Joel J. Kupperman - 2009 - The Journal of Ethics 13 (2-3):243-255.
    This paper represents two polemics. One is against suggestions (made by Harman and others) that recent psychological research counts against any claim that there is such a thing as genuine virtue (Cf. Harman, in: Byrne, Stalnaker, Wedgwood (eds.) Fact and value, pp 117–127, 2001 ). The other is against the view that virtue ethics should be seen as competing against such theories as Kantian ethics or consequentialism, particularly in the specification of decision procedures.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  5.  88
    Confucian civility.Joel J. Kupperman - 2010 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 9 (1):11-23.
    A major reason that Confucius should matter to Western ethical philosophers is that some of his concerns are markedly different from those most common in the West. A Western emphasis has been on major choices that are treated in a decontextualized way. Confucius’ emphasis is on paths of life, so that context matters. Further, the nuances of personal relations get more attention than is common (with the exception of feminist ethics) in Western philosophy. What Confucius provides is a valuable aid (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6.  61
    Confucius and the problem of naturalness.Joel J. Kupperman - 1968 - Philosophy East and West 18 (3):175-185.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7. Tradition and Community in the Formation of Character and Self.Joel J. Kupperman - 2004 - In Kwong-loi Shun & David B. Wong (eds.), Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 103--123.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8. Vulgar consequentialism.Joel J. Kupperman - 1980 - Mind 89 (355):321-337.
  9.  29
    Dimensions of Moral Creativity: Paradigms, Principles, and Ideals.Joel J. Kupperman - 1980 - Philosophy East and West 30 (1):123-125.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  94
    An anti‐essentialist view of the emotions.Joel J. Kupperman - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (4):341-351.
    Emotions normally include elements of feeling, motivation, and also intentionality; but the argument of this essay is that there can be emotion without feeling, emotion without corresponding motivation, and emotion without an intentional relation to an object such that the emotion is (among other things) a belief about or construal of it. Many recent writers have claimed that some form of intentionality is essential to emotion, and then have created lines of defence for this thesis. Thus, what look like troublesome (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. The epistemology of non-instrumental value.Joel J. Kupperman - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (3):659–680.
    Might there be knowledge of non-instrumental values? Arguments are give for two principal claims. One is that if there is such knowledge, it typically will have features that do not entirely match those of other kinds of knowledge. It will have a closer relation to the kind of person one is or becomes, and in the way it combines features of knowing-how with knowing-that. There also are problems of indeterminacy of non-instrumental value which are not commonly found in other things (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  11
    (1 other version)The Foundations of Morality.Joel J. Kupperman - 1983 - Philosophy 60 (234):552-554.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Why ethical philosophy needs to be comparative.Joel J. Kupperman - 2010 - Philosophy 85 (2):185-200.
    Principles can seem as entrenched in moral experience as Kant thinks space, time, and the categories are in human experience of the world. However not all cultures have such a view. Classical Indian and Chinese philosophies treat modification of the self as central to ethics. Decisions in particular cases and underlying principles are much less discussed. Ethics needs comparative philosophy in order not to be narrow in its concerns. A broader view can give weight to how people sometimes can change (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  69
    Moral realism and metaphysical anti-realism.Joel J. Kupperman - 1987 - Metaphilosophy 18 (2):95–107.
    The essay has two purposes. One is to point out connections and parallels between, On one hand, The debates of metaphysical realists and anti-Realists, And on the other hand, The debates surrounding moral realism. The second is to provide the outlines of a case for a kind of position that would generally be classified as moral realism. One feature of this position is that it emerges as parallel to, And compatible with, A metaphysical position that would generally be classified as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  10
    Classical and sour forms of virtue.Joel J. Kupperman - 2008 - In Paul Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest. New York: Oxford University Press.
    For the “respectable” part of society there can be a presumption of virtuousness, rather like the presumption of innocence in the law. In both cases, the presumption can be defeated, as we learn more and get into specifics. We still might insist that to be genuinely virtuous is to be able to pass the more familiar sorts of tests of virtue, and to be reliably virtuous also in the ordinary business of life, especially in things that really matter. Something like (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  44
    How values congeal into facts.Joel J. Kupperman - 2000 - Ratio 13 (1):37–53.
    The paper plays against the philosophical stereotype that facts are bits of reality, ‘furniture of the universe’, and that values in contrast are either mysterious bits of reality or responses to facts. It follows Strawson in regarding facts as interpretative constructs. Values also are interpretative constructs, characterized by a normal (but not universal) connection with motivations. So is there a deep difference? There is a sense of ‘facts’, marked by phrases such as ‘Stick to the facts’, in which the interpretative (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  34
    Comfort, hedonic treadmills, and public policy.Joel J. Kupperman - 2003 - Public Affairs Quarterly 17 (1):17-28.
  18.  45
    Ethics for Extraterrestrials.Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (4):311 - 320.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Confucius and the nature of religious ethics.Joel J. Kupperman - 1971 - Philosophy East and West 21 (2):189-194.
  20. A Case For Consequentialism.Joel J. Kupperman - 1981 - American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (4):305-313.
  21.  35
    For an Ontology of Morals: A Critique of Contemporary Ethical Theory.Joel J. Kupperman - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (2):244.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  26
    Nuance and ethical choice.Joel J. Kupperman - 1969 - Ethics 79 (2):105-114.
  23.  61
    Not in so many words: Chuang Tzu's strategies of communication.Joel J. Kupperman - 1989 - Philosophy East and West 39 (3):311-317.
  24.  28
    The Emotions of Altruism, East and West.Joel J. Kupperman - 1995 - In Roger Ames, Robert C. Solomon & Joel Marks (eds.), Emotions in Asian Thought: A Dialogue in Comparative Philosophy. SUNY Press. pp. 123.
  25.  7
    What is Character?Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - In Character. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    This chapter illustrates character as the fundamental facet of ethics. This book explores, analyzes, and defines character in different ways. Character involves habits and tendencies of thought and action that are not, or at least need not have been, original to a person. It has a vital role in how we act. It can provide the threads that bind together the various episodes and commitments of a person's life. The word personality is sometimes treated as interchangeable with character. On the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. A messy derivation of the categorical imperative.Joel J. Kupperman - 2002 - Philosophy 77 (4):485-502.
    Here are two widespread responses to Kant's categorical imperative. On one hand, one might note the absence of detailed rational derivation. On the other hand, even someone who maintains some skepticism is likely to have a sense that (nevertheless) there is something to Kant's central ideas. The recommended solution is analysis of elements of the categorical imperative. Their appeal turns out to have different sources. One aspect of the first formulation rests on the logic of normative utterances. But others can (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition, by Alasdair MacIntyre. [REVIEW]Joel J. Kupperman - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (3):737-740.
  28.  18
    (1 other version)Living Options in World Philosophy.Joel J. Kupperman - 1978 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (4):262-263.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. A New Look at the Logic of the - Relation.Joel J. Kupperman - 2005 - Philosophy 80 (3):343.
    In the 1950's some prominent philosophers suggested a logical relation weaker than entailment between primarily descriptive statements and ethical conclusions. The paper revisits this suggestion. It examines four ways in which ethical statemnts can be supported by descriptions and evaluations. This provides a similarity bteween some kinds of reason-giving in ethics and familiar cases of logical inference, making it plausible to speak of a logic. The similarity however is limited, and the strength in ethics of descriptive reasons is never precise (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  96
    Axiological Realism.Joel J. Kupperman - 1996 - Philosophy 71 (276):185 - 203.
    Many would consider the lengthening debate between moral realists and anti-realists to be draw-ish. Plainly new approaches are needed. Or might the issue, which most broadly concerns realism in relation to normative judgments, be broken down into parts or sectors? Physicists have been saying, in relation to a similarly longstanding debate, that light in some respects behaves like waves and in some respects like particles. Might realism be more plausible in relation to some kinds of normative judgments than others?
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  34
    Ethical fallibility.Joel J. Kupperman - 1988 - Ratio 1 (1):33-46.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  78
    Art and aesthetic experience.Joel J. Kupperman - 1975 - British Journal of Aesthetics 15 (1):29-39.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Autonomy and the Very Limited Role of Advocacy in the Classroom.Joel J. Kupperman - 1996 - The Monist 79 (4):488-498.
    My thesis is that advocacy in the classroom is rarely appropriate with regard to live moral, political, or social issues, and for that matter not always appropriate with regard to issues within a discipline. By advocacy I mean a teacher's presenting a view as her or his own in a way that might well elicit students' agreement. My argument against advocacy is supported by two sets of assumptions. One concerns the aims of higher education. The other concerns a distinction between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  29
    Aesthetic Value.Joel J. Kupperman - 1972 - American Philosophical Quarterly 9 (3):259 - 264.
  35.  13
    Character and Responsibility.Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - In Character. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Are we responsible for our characters? This question is the heart of this chapter. People are responsible for their characters because they chose them. Holding people responsible for their characters, even if these are largely involuntary, is effective and functional in a way in which holding people responsible for involuntary actions is not. People should be responsible and liable both for their characters and for actions that flow from their characters. The fact of the matter is whether someone is responsible (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  6
    Character and Self.Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - In Character. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    This chapter describes character as a second self or, on the other hand, as a first self. To understand the importance of character in human life, we must appreciate who it is that has a character. Full understanding of what character is will have to include the background of a metaphysical account of the self. The self is a relation which relates itself to its own self, or it is that in the relation that the relation relates to its own (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Confucius, Mencius, Hume and Kant on reason and choice.Joel J. Kupperman - 1989 - In Shlomo Bidermann & Ben Ami Scharfstein (eds.), Rationality in question: on Eastern and Western views of rationality. New York: E.J. Brill. pp. 119--139.
  38.  36
    Chisholm's view of person and object.Joel J. Kupperman - 1979 - Metaphilosophy 10 (1):62–73.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  57
    Do we desire only pleasure?Joel J. Kupperman - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 34 (4):451 - 454.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  7
    Ethical Theory and Choice.Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - In Character. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    This chapter explores ways in which an ethical theory can develop through time and, in particular, variations in Kantian ethical theories. The chapter argues that a Kantian could say that we have duties to particular people as part of ongoing commitments, but an adequate and sufficient account of good and poor decisions in personal relationships cannot be based entirely on the categorical imperative, nor can we do justice to seriously wrong decisions by regarding them as violations of duty. Any ethical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  43
    Felt and unfelt emotions: A rejoinder to Dalgleish.Joel J. Kupperman - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (1):91.
  42.  18
    Francis Hutcheson: Morality and Nature.Joel J. Kupperman - 1985 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (2):195 - 202.
  43.  66
    Half-truths.Joel J. Kupperman - 2012 - Ratio 25 (2):148-163.
    Half-truths are statements that have some insight or truth in them, but do not amount to a final or definitive truth that all competent judges should be able to accept. Complete truth requires that the relevant interpretative structures can be taken for granted, and can be expected to be understood by all competent language users. Disciplines such as philosophy, history, and sociology do contain a small number of complete truths, concerning some logical relations or such matters as the year of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  8
    Human Nature: A Reader.Joel J. Kupperman (ed.) - 2012 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    This anthology provides a set of distinctive, influential views that explore the mysteries of human nature from a variety of perspectives. It can be read on its own, or in conjunction with Joel Kupperman’s text, _Theories of Human Nature_.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  28
    Investigations of the self.Joel J. Kupperman - 1984 - Philosophy East and West 34 (1):37-51.
  46.  46
    Is the Nature of Physical Reality Unknowable?Joel J. Kupperman - 1978 - American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (2):99 - 105.
  47.  7
    Justice and the Virtues.Joel J. Kupperman - 1991 - In Character. New York, US: Oup Usa.
    This chapter investigates the idea of unity of virtues by analyzing justice. The nature of justice cannot be appreciated without a prior understanding of the limited scope of the word and of the concerns that are related to it. Justice is an artificial virtue that has to be qualified. To be a just person is to make appropriate decisions in some of the areas in which one deals with other people. Virtues can have important and visible links with other areas (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    Precision in history.Joel J. Kupperman - 1975 - Mind 84 (335):374-389.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  61
    Reasons In Support of Evaluations of Works of Art.Joel J. Kupperman - 1966 - The Monist 50 (2):222-236.
    Critics often give reasons in support of their evaluations of works of art. They say, for example, that a work is bad because it is repetitive, or the characters are not well-delineated, or the colors are too uniformly bright. Or they say that a work is good because of the delicate balance of colors, its wit and excitement, or the way in which each variation of the theme is fresh and yet related to the previous variation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  38
    Reply to David Wong.Joel J. Kupperman - 1986 - Philosophy East and West 36 (3):283.
1 — 50 / 64